Hands Off Clitoridectomy
What our revulsion reveals about ourselves.
Yael Tamir
Not since Masters and Johnson has the clitoris --
or its absence -- been a topic of such intense debate. In discussions about
multiculturalism, clitoridectomy is now the trump card, taking over the role
once played by cannibalism, slavery, lynchings, or the Indian tradition of Sati:
"Is this the kind of tradition you would like to protect?" liberals ask
embarrassed multiculturalists, who immediately qualify their cultural pluralism.
Clitoridectomy defines the boundary between us and them, between cultures we can
tolerate and those we must condemn.
Clitoridectomy is obviously a deplorable practice. It is, among other things,
an extremely painful, traumatizing mutilation of young girls that leaves them
permanently disfigured and deprived of sexual enjoyment. We should express no
sympathy toward those who practice it, and support those who struggle to end
it.
But we also should be suspicious about the role of
clitoridectomy in current political debate. Despite their liberal
appearance, references to clitoridectomy commonly reveal a patronizing
attitude toward women, suggesting that they are primarily sexual beings.
Moreover, those references involve a certain degree of dishonesty. They
intentionally widen the gap between our culture and those in which
clitoridectomy is practiced, thus presenting those other cultures as
incommensurable with ours. The effect of this distancing is to disconnect
criticism of their practices from criticism of our own, and turn
reflection on other cultures into yet another occasion for celebrating our
special virtues. We should resist such self-congratulation. And if we do,
the debate about clitoridectomy takes on an entirely different cast.
|
|
But when is the body improved and when is it mutilated? In
most cases, the answer depends on one's conception of
beauty.
|
The most straightforward objection to
clitoridectomy is that it is a painful procedure, imposed on young girls, and
performed in conditions which could lead to permanent damage. This is all true,
and part of what makes the practice so objectionable. But it could not be the
whole of the matter. After all, removing a tooth is also a painful procedure,
often imposed on children, and if performed in non-hygienic conditions, it can
produce permanent damage. But we are not horrified and disgusted by evidence
that such treatments are the norm in some parts of the world, and that many
children suffer greatly as a result.
Moreover, we are all aware of painful practices of body piercing, tattooing,
and abnormal elongation of lips, ear lobes, and necks. National
Geographic runs cover photos of women and men who have undergone such severe
malformations, not in protest but as a neutral representation of other ways of
life with their different conceptions of beauty. So hostility to clitoridectomy
is not driven principally by concerns about physical suffering. Those who object
to it would be no less hostile if it were performed in hygienic conditions under
anesthesia.
It might be said that these examples are all irrelevant as they do not
include the mutilation of the body. But when is the body improved and
when is it mutilated? Are parents who force their children to wear braces
mutilating their children's teeth or improving them? In most cases, the answer
depends on one's conception of beauty. Because we tend to see straight, white
teeth as beautiful, and a sign of good health, we spend lots of money inflicting
pain and inconvenience upon our children to achieve this goal. To be sure,
parents say (sincerely) that these treatments will improve their children's life
chances, self-image, and social standing. But parents who perform clitoridectomy
on their daughters invoke precisely the same arguments.
Furthermore, it seems clear that Western conceptions of female beauty
encourage women to undergo a wide range of painful, medically unnecessary, and
potentially damaging processes -- extreme diets, depilation, face lifts, fat
pumping, silicone implants. Of course, adult women do these things to their own
bodies, and, it is said, their decisions are freely made. But would our gut
reaction to female circumcision be very different if it were performed on
consenting adults? It is not unlikely that girls at the age of 13 or 14, who are
considered in traditional societies as adults mature enough to wed and bear
children, would "consent" to the mutilation of their bodies if they were
convinced that marriage and children were contingent on so doing. Many women who
followed the tradition of Sati seemed to do it as a matter of choice. Did their
"consent" make this tradition defensible? Women "consent" to such practices
because the alternative is even more painful -- a life of solitude, humiliation,
and deprivation.
One may argue that these traditions are objectionable because their
persistence fosters false consciousness, which in turn leads women to make such
choices. But our own culture fosters false beliefs of a similar kind. According
to Naomi Wolf's The Beauty Myth, some 75 percent of women aged 18-35
believe that they are fat, whereas only 25 percent are medically
overweight.1 Still more heartbreaking is the fact that the majority
of the 30,000 women who responded to a Glamour questionnaire preferred
losing 10-15 pounds to success in work or in love. So the fostering of such
beliefs cannot differentiate their culture from our own and explain our
hostility to it.
Perhaps, then, we object to clitoridectomy because it is performed on minors.
But think of the parents in our culture who foster in their daughters bad eating
habits that might destroy their teeth or their vital organs, or, in more tragic
cases, lead to life-threatening eating disorders. Are we ready to judge these
parents as harshly as we judge parents who require clitoridectomies?
In both cases, parents sincerely believe that they are serving the interests
of their children and allowing them to live what is, according to their
conception of the good, a meaningful life. Both cases may thus be taken to
demonstrate that parents are not the most trustworthy guardians of their
children, but why should one case be more harshly judged than the other?
Because clitoridectomy is permanent, whereas other undesirable outcomes are
reversible? Yet irreversibility is a problem only if the outcome is undesirable.
In what way are the consequences of clitoridectomy undesirable?
The common answer is that clitoridectomy damages
women's sexual organs, thus depriving them of sexual enjoyment -- a basic need,
perhaps even a right. One may wonder, however, when precisely our society became
so deeply committed to women's sexual enjoyment.
As we know -- from Masters and Johnson to the Hite report -- many women in
our own society rarely, if at all, experience sexual enjoyment. We are also
aware that many features of our society turn women against their own bodies and
encourage them to suppress their sexuality. The high frequency of rapes or
attempted rapes, childhood sexual abuse, the battering of women, and exposure to
pornography limits women's sexual expression and enjoyment. Bodily self-hatred,
encouraged by the introduction of unrealizable standards of beauty -- teenage
models, Barbie dolls, or even children's fairy-tales -- fosters frustration and
feelings of inadequacy.
From Cinderella to Lady D., from Playboy to children's cartoons, the
ideal woman is portrayed as a thin, delicate creature with large breasts, a
narrow waist, and a limited intellect. Those who do not measure up may spend a
lifetime of "self-improvement" and encounter permanent feelings of failure and
disgust. Feminists have argued that these phenomena have devastating effects on
the ability of women to enjoy sex, and yet very little is done in our society to
change the nature of this oppressive reality. Perhaps, then, we are not as
committed to assuring women the ability to experience sexual enjoyment as we
seem to be when we condemn clitoridectomy.
The difference may be that the damage to women's sexual lives is an
unintended consequence of the undesirable features of our own society, whereas
this is the aim of clitoridectomy. Perhaps the intentionality makes the act
particularly repellent. If so, we should be much less forgiving of parents who,
for religious reasons, teach their daughters that sex in general and
masturbation in particular are obscene, thus eliciting fear and revulsion at
sexual activities. This damage may be psychological rather than physical. But if
limited sexual enjoyment is the issue, why should the particular nature of the
harm matter so much? It is indeed a striking feature of our society that we are
so much more liberal with parents who inflict permanent psychological damage on
their children than with parents who slap them or do not take proper care of
their clothing or personal hygiene. The different ways in which we react to
visible and invisible damages is disturbing; though our reaction to visible
injuries is based on aesthetic as well as moral disgust, it is inconsistent with
what we know of the severity of mental injuries.
We come closer to the reason why arguments against clitoridectomy are so
troubling if we focus on what is special about sex organs. An implicit
assumption in these arguments is that if there were no physiological barrier to
sexual enjoyment, women's lives would greatly improve. But perhaps we should
remind ourselves that women are not merely sexual agents, that their ability to
lead rich and rewarding lives does not depend solely on the nature of their sex
life. Are we moving from an age in which female orgasms could not be publicly
discussed, in which women were supposed to "endure" sex for the sake of
childbearing, to one in which the right to multiple orgasms will be the
principal emblem of women's liberation?
One cannot help thinking that the gut reaction of many men against
clitoridectomy reflects the fact that in our society the sexual enjoyment of
women is seen as a measure of the sexual power and achievements of men. Men in
our society are more intimidated by women who do not enjoy orgasms than by those
who do. In societies in which clitoridectomies are performed, men are more
intimidated by women who do enjoy their body and their sexuality. In both cases,
a masculine yardstick measures the value of female sexuality.
It is important to remember that the first champion of women's right to
sexual pleasure, the sexologist Havelock Ellis, strongly opposed women's social
liberation. He opposed women's employment outside the home, and firmly believed
that "every healthy woman ought to exercise her productive function at least
once in her lifetime, and asserted that women's brains were in a certain sense .
. . in their womb."2 The right of women to enjoy their sexuality, he
argued, was independent of their right to equal standing in the society; the
former right, he thought, was to be seen as prior to, or worse, a substitute
for, a whole set of political and economic freedoms.
A fulfilling sex life is certainly one good, but there are others. Nuns take
an oath of celibacy, but we do not usually condemn the church for preventing its
clergy from enjoying an active sex life. Moreover, most of us do not think that
Mother Teresa is leading a worse life than Chichulina, though the latter claims
to have experienced an extensive number of orgasms.
It is true that nuns are offered spiritual life in exchange for earthly
goods, but in the societies where clitoridectomy is performed, the fulfilling
life of motherhood and child bearing are offered in exchange. Some may rightly
claim that one can function as a wife and a mother while still experiencing
sexual pleasures. Others believe that full devotion to God does not require an
oath of celibacy. Yet these views are, after all, a matter of convention. Hence,
the problem with clitoridectomy cannot be the deprivation of sexual experiences.
A thought experiment might be helpful here. Suppose that anthropologists
discover a new tribe in the woods of Libidia. In this tribe young females who
reach the age of sexual maturity are forced to go through a ceremony in which
their clitoris is manipulated in a way that they are more likely to experience
lengthy and extremely enjoyable orgasms. The ceremony is quite pleasant,
performed by women, and not at all humiliating.
As a result, the women of Libidia turn nymphomaniac. Consequently, they lack
the concentration needed to perform any serious task. They drop out of school,
have limited career prospects, and become completely dependent on male support.
Hence, women are marginalized socially, economically, and politically: They own
no property, hold no political or economic positions, do not participate in the
political process, and have no social influence.
In protest against this tradition, members of a feminist group decide to
undergo clitoridectomy. They follow the Amazons, who, according to legend, would
amputate their right breast to be able to comfortably carry quivers and be free
in the exercise of warfare. In mutilating themselves, the women of Libidia free
themselves of any reliance on men and are able to pursue their social and
political goals. Sexual enjoyment, they argue, is important, but experiencing it
is no assurance of living a meaningful life. Is there anything wrong with such a
practice?
Sexual enjoyment has acquired a mythical status in our society, advocated
both as the most sublime and most corruptive pleasure. Advocates of
clitoridectomy see the corruption: Performing clitoridectomy will restrict the
sexual desires of women, thereby turning them into more chaste and righteous
wives and mothers. They believe that the pursuit of sexual pleasures may lead a
person astray, and that women are more likely to be influenced by such desires
and act unscrupulously.
Both assumptions are also well grounded in the Western tradition. The failure
to control the pursuit of sexual pleasures was seen by religious thinkers, as
well as by many secular liberals, as undermining virtue, fostering bad habits
and pernicious behavior, and hindering the possibility of true love (either of
God or of other human beings). In the Christian tradition celibacy was affirmed
as the highest ideal, and "sex within marriage was regarded as an evil necessary
for the continuation of the species."3
|
But if we will object to clitoridectomy on socio-political
grounds -- yet another way of oppressing women -- the argument
will have clear implications for our own society.
| The assumption that women are weak-willed and feeble-minded
is also well founded in Western schools of thought. From Plato to Kant to
Kohlberg, a long line of philosophers and social thinkers has urged that
women are naturally lighthearted, prone to temptation, and therefore less
able to practice self-restraint and think in moral terms. More likely than
men to be corrupted, they need special guidance, restraint, and
protection. Freud added that women who require clitoral stimulus are
victims of arrested development. Mature individuals redirect their sexual
desires "into creativity in the arts, sciences, politics, business,
religion, and other non-sexual activities. Repression takes its toll on
the individual psyche, but a necessary toll. Repression is
civilization.4 |
What is wrong with this attitude
toward female sexuality -- whether expressed by clitoridectomy, the Libidian
tradition, or our own culture -- is its social purpose: to use sex as a means of
subjecting women and depriving them of their chance to participate in society as
equals. The major problem with clitoridectomy, then, is socio-political.
Clitoridectomy is yet another way of oppressing women and locking them at home,
of seeing them as the producers of children and as a source of pleasure to
others. But if we will object to clitoridectomy on these grounds, the argument
will seem very familiar, and will have clear implications for our own society.
Michael Walzer has argued that every morality has both a thin universal
dimension and a thick contextualized content.5 The same is true of
wickedness. Societies discriminate, dominate, and abuse their members in various
ways, but there is something common to all expressions of oppression. We should
place this core aspect, repeated in all traditions in different forms, at the
center of our criticism. In the cases discussed here, it is not a particular
practice but a set of ill-motivated efforts to control the sexuality of women
and to restrict their ability to compete for social and political resources that
we should find reprehensible.
Does the overwhelming disgust at clitoridectomy signal an emerging social
commitment to structural change -- to ensuring equal social, economic, and
political status for women? I'm afraid not. Of course, the absence of such
commitment is no justification for clitoridectomy. My purpose, however, is not
to justify clitoridectomy, but to expose the roots of the deep hostility to it
-- to reveal the smug, unjustified self-satisfaction lurking behind the current
condemnation of clitoridectomy. Referring to clitoridectomy, and emphasizing the
distance of the practice from our own conventions, allows us to condemn
them for what they do to their women, support the struggle of
their women against their primitive, inhuman culture, and remain silent
on the status of women in our society.
|
Multicultural exchanges raise acute concerns because they
confront us with our own deficiencies.
|
It is time, then, to hold off on using the
example of clitoridectomy. But this discussion also carries a more
fundamental implication for current debate on multiculturalism. As I
indicated at the outset, too often and too easily this debate produces
condemnations of cultures other than our own. We do not usually discuss
the way different cultures oppress women and compare our modes of
oppression to theirs, but instead we ask, completely oblivious to our own
vices, How can they do that to them? Yet as we have seen,
their cultures show considerable continuity with ours.
|
Multicultural exchanges raise acute concerns not
because they point to the incommensurability of cultures, or the impossibility
of cross-cultural conversation, but because they confront us with our own
deficiencies. Through them we are able to identify the roots of our own
prejudices and injustices and see the devastating outcomes that may issue from
them. One way to counter the anxiety such exchanges may incite is to concentrate
on practices that appear to be as distant from our own tradition as possible.
When we look closely at these practices, the differences start to fade. It is
thus time to approach multicultural exchanges with a sharper vision of our own
vices, and see the multicultural debate less as a way to understand them
and correct their ways than as a way to understand and improve our own
culture.
Originally published in the Summer 1996 issue
of Boston Review
Copyright Boston Review, 1993–2003. All
rights reserved. Please do not reproduce without permission.
|
|
|